A. philosophy - passion to understand the meaning of everything
Source: Johnson, James A., Dupuis, Victor L., Musial, Diann, Hall, Gene E., and Gollnick, Donna M. Introductions
to Foundations of American Education. 11th edition. Boston: Allyn and Bacon, 1999.
NATURALISM IS TODAY--BY HISTORY, PHILOSOPHY, AND PURPOSE--AN ESSENTIAL
PART OF SCIENCE
by
Steven D. Schafersman
Department of Geology
Miami University
Oxford,
OH 45056
schafesd@muohio.edu
Verachte nur Vernunft und Wissenschaft,
des Menschen allerhöchste Kraft,
laß nur in Blend- und Zauberwerken
dich
von dem Lügengeist bestärken,
so hab' ich dich schon unbedingt.
Mephistopheles in Goethe's Faust [1]
Introduction
Naturalism is, ironically, a controversial philosophy. Our modern civilization depends totally for
its existence and future survival on the methods and fruits of science, naturalism is the philosophy that science created
and that science now follows with such success, yet the great majority of humans (at least 90% of the U.S. population) believe
in the antithesis of naturalism--supernaturalism. Our culture persistently indulges and celebrates supernaturalism, and most
people, including some scientists, refuse to systematically understand naturalism and its consequences. This paper proposes
to show that naturalism is essential to the success of scientific understanding, and it examines and criticizes the claims
of pseudoscientists and theistic philosophers that science should employ supernatural explanations as part of its normal practice.
Along the way I will speculate briefly on the reasons why such individuals are today advocating what would appear to be such
an oxymoronic conjunction as supernaturalistic science (or worse, theistic science). Also, quite a bit of this essay is devoted
to examining basic concepts in metaphysics and the philosophy of science, since there seems to be some confusion about them.
Definitions
Naturalism is
"a species of philosophical monism according to which whatever exists or happens is natural in the sense of being
susceptible to explanation through methods which, although paradigmatically exemplified in the natural sciences, are continuous
from domain to domain of objects and events...[thus, there cannot] exist any entities or events which lie, in principle, beyond
the scope of scientific explanation" (Danto, 1967, p. 448);
"the view that nature is all there is and all basic truths are truths of nature" (Audi, 1984, p. 372);
"the twofold view that (1) everything is composed of natural entities--those studied in the sciences--whose properties
determine all the properties of things, persons included, ...abstract entities... like possibilities...and mathematical objects...and
(2) acceptable methods of justification and explanation are commensurable, in some sense, with those in science" (Post, 1995,
p. 517);
"the view that everything is natural, i.e. that everything there is belongs to the world of nature, and so can be studied
by the methods appropriate for studying that world..." (Lacey, 1995, p. 604);
"the philosophical movement that "wishes to use the methods of science, evidence, and reason to understand nature and
the place of human species within it"..."skeptical of the postulation of a transcendental realm beyond nature, or of the claim
that nature can be understood without using the methods of reason and evidence"... and "the philosophical generalization of
the methods and conclusions of the sciences" (Kurtz, 1990, p. 7, 12).
In my own definition, a synthesis of those above, naturalism is the philosophy that maintains that
(1) nature is all there is and whatever exists or happens is natural; (2) nature (the universe or cosmos) consists only of
natural elements, that is, of spatiotemporal material elements--matter and energy--and non-material elements--mind, ideas,
values, logical relationships, etc.--that are either associated with the human brain or exist independently of the brain and
are therefore somehow immanent in the structure of the universe; (3) nature works by natural processes that follow natural
laws, and all can, in principle, be explained and understood by science and philosophy; and (4) the supernatural does not
exist, i.e., only nature is real, therefore, supernature is non-real. Naturalism is therefore a metaphysical position opposed
mainly by supernaturalism. It is not an ethical system, although a variety--pragmatic naturalism, a synthesis of pragmatism
and naturalism--does develop ethical positions. Furthermore, naturalism is a subset of metaphysical realism.
Is naturalism true? I think so, but I can't know for certain. Naturalism's truth would presumably
depend on the existence of a supernatural realm. If there was empirical evidence for the supernatural or a logical reason
to believe in it without such evidence, then naturalism would be false. If we knew for certain that the supernatural did not
exist, then naturalism would be true. But if there is no evidence for the supernatural and no reason to believe in it despite
the lack of evidence (both of which are the case), the supernatural could still possibly exist without our knowledge. Such
a lack of evidence and reason forces one to be agnostic about the existence of the supernatural and thus about the ultimate
truth of naturalism. However, because of such lack of evidence and logical argument, it is most reasonable to disbelieve the
supernatural and believe that naturalism is true.
Fortunately, whatever we think about the supernatural, we may all agree that a natural world exists.
Naturalism could be accepted as the most reasonably true philosophy by examining and justifying it's statements as a scientist
would examine and justify the statements of a scientific theory. In scientific terms, the truth of naturalism could be considered
reliable knowledge, since naturalism's statements have a great amount of empirical evidence in support of them, it has a highly-reasoned
logical structure, and the statements of this logical structure have been repeatedly tested and corroborated. Such a truth,
however, as with all such scientific truths, must be treated skeptically and held tentatively, since it is only reliable knowledge,
not absolute, ultimate truth (whatever that is). This idea of demonstrating the truth of a philosophy by the same means one
would use in the scientific method to investigate natural elements (examining empirical evidence, using logical reasoning,
skeptically testing one's claims to achieve corroboration, etc.) seems reasonable to me, but it may not seem so to more knowledgeable
philosophers. But I have no better justification for naturalism's truth than this scientific one.
Even though naturalism has two primary sources in philosophy, "materialism in metaphysics and empiricism
[and skepticism] in epistemology" (Kurtz, 1990, p. 12), naturalism does not necessitate a commitment to materialism, a philosophy
with which it is often confused (more on this below). Materialism recognizes the existence of non-material elements, but claims
that they are unconditionally produced by or associated with material elements, that is, the non-material elements would not
exist if the material elements did not exist. Certainly most philosophical naturalists today are materialists, and methodological
materialism is probably universally adopted among scientists today, but idealism or dualism could be true and naturalism would
still be viable. Some of the early positivists were phenomenalists (phenomenology is a type of idealism). Furthermore, non-material
elements (such as the conscious mind) undoubtedly exist, and their relation to or association with the material world (such
as the brain) is still problematical and a concern of both scientific investigation and philosophical analysis (e.g., Dennett,
1991, 1996). I reference Daniel Dennett, a noted philosopher, to show that the overwhelming belief among scientists that mind
is a function of matter, the brain, is still legitimately the subject of philosophic analysis, even though Dennett uses our
scientific knowledge of brain and consciousness to ultimately defend an entirely naturalistic and materialistic interpretation.
The above authors and I would agree, therefore, that naturalism is much broader in scope than materialism,
and could entertain a wide diversity of metaphysical positions, such as idealism or materialism, monism or dualism, atheism,
and even theism, since a natural deity could be conceived as one immanent in the universe (pantheism) or contained in the
self. Idealism, dualism, and theism are therefore legitimate stances within naturalism but, for a number of reasons, are not
very popular. Individuals who would normally believe such things are usually already supernaturalists, and so don't care about
these tiny subcategories of naturalism. Metaphysics in this context is important, and I reject the positivist idea that metaphysics
is cognitively meaningless and that science alone provides genuine knowledge, since I believe that science itself is based
on a number of highly-developed philosophies (epistemologies), as explained below.
Supernaturalism, the antithesis of naturalism, includes belief in supernatural beings (gods, goddesses,
lesser deities, angels, devils, fairies, trolls, leprechauns, ghosts, wood nymphs, etc.), their activities (miracles, raising
from the dead, faith healing, virgin birth, life after death, communication between living and dead, communication between
human and god, ritual symbolic cannibalism of the avatar, etc.), their realms (heaven, hell, spirit worlds, etc.), and their
concerns (transcendence, sanctification, salvation, sin, immortal souls, spirits, etc.)--in short, belief in superstition
from the highest to the lowest. Since everyone agrees that the natural exists, it is the responsibility of the supernaturalists
to demonstrate the existence of the supernatural. This they have not done.
Although some may disagree with me about this, it is obvious that there is no empirical evidence for
supernatural elements and no reason to believe in them despite the lack of evidence, but their overwhelming popularity makes
naturalism a distinctly minority philosophy among popular philosophies today, especially in the United States. Belief by wishful,
hopeful, and emotional faith is the most common way belief in the supernatural is promoted and justified, but that is not
the issue here. We are concerned with the relationship of science and naturalism, whether science assumes or necessitates
methodological or ontological naturalism or both, and whether supernaturalism can or should be a part of science.
What is Science?
Science is a truth-seeking, problem-solving, method of inquiry. The reliability of its scientific
method depends on the correctness of three ancient philosophies that science uses: empiricism, rationalism, and skepticism.
This strange combination of epistemologies--for historically they were at odds with each other, and in extreme form remain
so today--was used and molded by scientists through the centuries to construct modern science. Empirical evidence is used
to propose hypotheses which logically explain natural causes by predicting natural effects; because explanations might be
fallacious, hypotheses are skeptically tested by additional empirical observations or experiments to see if their predictions
are fulfilled; if so, the corroborated hypotheses are used to construct logical theories that explain the universe. This one
sentence describes a method so powerful that it has profoundly and irrevocably changed human society, culture, and philosophy.
I can't defend the truth of these three philosophies here, and perhaps I don't need to, but I do acknowledge
that these three epistemologies are logically and methodologically prior to science, although I believe that scientists (including
"natural philosophers") were the individuals first responsible for rigorously practicing them, demonstrating their truth,
and in some cases (e.g., Aristotle), first analyzing and explaining them. Today these three epistemologies are taught in schools
as "critical thinking," a methodology indistinguishable, in my opinion, from scientific thinking. This point cannot be made
too strongly. Paul Kurtz (1990, p. 7) states, for example, that "Science is not interpreted as an esoteric method of inquiry,
but is continuous with standards of critical intelligence used in common, ordinary life." I have long told students--as a
justification for university science requirements--that, because they will learn scientific thinking in their science courses,
they will learn critical thinking, the best and most reliable type of thinking, that will enable them to successfully solve
problems and answer questions throughout their lives. I am not aware how grateful they are for this justification, but it's
convincing to me.
Science uses critical thinking to discover new and reliable knowledge about nature; critical thinking
can be used in all other aspects of life as well. Critical thinking has been epitomized as "the scientific method" in science,
simply because scientists must practice it to be successful, so it is in science that critical thinking finds its most thorough-going
and rigorous praxis. But critical thinking is also used in business, government, jurisprudence, the arts, the humanities,
the social sciences, and especially philosophy. Natural science has no monopoly on critical thinking, or on the empiricism,
rationalism, and skepticism that underlie it. Science is the most visible practitioner of critical thinking, since its use
in the other disciplines is less pervasive, although it is highly valued in the social sciences and the humanities. Indeed,
non-critical types of thinking--authoritative, emotional, wishful, hopeful, subjective, biased, persuasive thinking--are often
just as popular and successful as critical thinking in these other disciplines, so it is sometimes not valued as highly as
it is in science. My major point, however, is that critical inquiry is humanity's surest path to reliable knowledge in all
areas of inquiry.
Later in this paper, I will demonstrate that naturalism is a methodological necessity in the practice
of science by scientists, and an ontological necessity for the understanding and credibility of science by scientists. The
alternative to naturalism is supernaturalism; unless naturalism is true and supernaturalism false, empiricism--comprehending
reality solely by sensory experience--is not sufficient to comprehend reality; rationalism--the use of logic in reasoning--is
not sufficient to understand reality; and skepticism--the questioning and evaluation of one's knowledge system and beliefs--is
not sufficient to arrive at reliable knowledge of reality. Naturalism implies a unity and lawfulness in nature, a condition
in which nature's reality can be objectively understood, without which the pursuit of scientific knowledge would be useless.
But naturalism is not an assumption or presupposition on the part of scientists, a common claim of critics; it is, instead,
a hypothesis that has been tested and repeatedly corroborated, and so has become reliable knowledge itself.
I have attempted to demonstrate the truth of naturalism by using the same methods (evidence, reason,
testing, corroboration) that one would use to demonstrate the truth of some fact or theory of nature. Whatever the value of
such an attempt, the question now is: How can one justify confidence in the scientific method? That is, how can one demonstrate
that the reliable knowledge that science produces is the best, most truthful knowledge that humans can obtain, and that it
should therefore be believed in preference to knowledge obtained by other methods of knowing? Entire books have been written
to answer these questions using sophisticated logical and epistemological arguments (mostly older books by neopositivists--such
books are less common now!); I could reference them, but will refrain. Instead, I will justify the reliability of scientific
method by a single pragmatic argument: Of all human disciplines or methods of inquiry, science alone has fulfilled its promises
of a better, progressive, greater understanding of and control over nature. Humans depend on science--and its applied offshoot,
engineering--for food, clothing, shelter, energy, medicine, communication, transportation, information, weapons, entertainment,
etc. Our modern civilization would collapse without the continued support of science. No other human endeavor can make these
claims; science, solely because of its method, is the most successful human endeavor in history. The others don't even come
close. Because of the immense and continuing success of science, it and scientists have achieved great legitimacy and prestige
among both intellectuals and the public. This fact will be important later in this essay.
Phillip Johnson (1995, p. 68) calls this argument the "argument from success," and although he recognizes
it as a good argument, he criticizes it by claiming that "all statements made in the name of science are not equally reliable,"
and the technical achievements of science are not on the same level as statements concerning such "vast theoretical scenarios"
as the prebiotic chemical origin of life, evolutionary biology, and cosmology. Johnson's counter-argument is fallacious, of
course; all scientific statements are the product of an identical method and therefore have the same reliability. Johnson
may be surprised to learn that safe bridges, electronic appliances, hybrid crops, reliable and abundant energy, and the things
he mentions, "airplanes, nuclear bombs, antibiotics and computers," all depend on "vast theoretical scenarios" for their existence
and success. They all depend on the reliable theoretical structure of science. But perhaps he knew this, and merely was using
the common creationist tactic of falsely distinguishing technical "facts" from scientific "theories." Scientists have as much
confidence in the theory of evolution and they do in other scientific theories; all that scientists really have, after all,
are theories, which merely consist of the most reliable knowledge that humans can possess. As another example of Johnson's
misrepresentation in this context, he says that scientists freely concede that "the materialistic theory of mind is only a
hypothesis" (p. 69). Of course it is a hypothesis, a highly reliable hypothesis that has been tested and corroborated to such
an extent that it can legitimately be considered a fact, something of such reliability that only someone irrational or perverse
could deny it. "Only a hypothesis" and "just a theory" must be the most frequent phrases found in any computer word search
of the creationist literature.
The Limits of Science
Since I am a scientist speaking at a philosophy conference, perhaps I should clarify some issues.
Some may suggest that my defense of science is an example of scientism. Scientism has been defined as "the belief that science,
especially natural science, is much the most valuable part of human learning--much the most valuable part because it is much
the most authoritative, or serious, or beneficial" (Sorell, 1991, p. 1). I would say that this definition is an overstatement,
especially since it is exactly what I believe, and I am not scientistic. Scientism is, rather, the belief that science is
the only valuable part of human learning, that knowledge comes only through the methods of investigation available
to science, that science by itself gives us reliable answers to questions about morality and epistemology, that science
enables us to solve all serious human problems, and that science will give us a comprehensive and unified understanding
of the meaning of the universe. I believe none of these. Science may illuminate serious ethical, epistemological, aesthetic,
and metaphysical problems and suggest solutions, but, in the end, many human problems must find solutions in human philosophies,
even if the answers are unsatisfactory for a variety of reasons.
Science does give us reliable knowledge about the material universe, that is, about everything in
the universe that is matter or energy. Reliable knowledge, or justified true belief, is knowledge that has a high probability
of being true because it has been justified by a reliable method. Furthermore, science is not just the best method--it is
the only method that humans possess (at least, the only one discovered so far) that provides such reliable knowledge
about the material world. Other ways of knowing about the material world give us knowledge of nature, certainly, but that
knowledge is not reliable, for it may be true or false and we can't be sure which. Non-scientific methods, therefore, don't
even come close to science as a method of understanding and explaining the cosmos. Since we humans are ourselves material,
inhabit a material world, and depend on this material world for our existence, sustenance, and survival, it seems to me that
the discipline that allows us to reliably understand and control the material world must be much the most valuable part of
human learning. But not the only part.
Science is less reliable if we examine more difficult questions about the relationship of the material
world to the immaterial world of the conscious mind: the world of thoughts, ideas, beliefs, dreams, truths, values, morals,
meanings, purposes, intentions, reasons, logical relationships, imagination, free will, and self-awareness. All of these things
are undoubtedly part of the natural world, and science certainly helps to investigate them and provide reliable knowledge
to help us understand them, but, on its own, it has not provided reliable answers to questions about them, and I'm not sure
that, in principle, it can. Philosophy is required along with science in our investigation of the immaterial world, although
their combined reliability is no sure thing, either. The immaterial world includes, of course, the nature of truth and knowledge,
and therefore the ultimate reliability, certainty, and objectivity of scientific knowledge. Thus, I am happy to acknowledge
the vital importance of philosophy in the effort to explain how science works. I emphasize that science and philosophy are
both involved in understanding and explaining all non-material aspects of nature. Furthermore, I emphasize that philosophy
of science explains how science works--it does not and should not tell scientists how to work. (This final point
is important in our present discussion, in which theistic philosophers are insisting that science consider the supernatural
in its practice.)
We turn now to the really difficult, perhaps intractable, questions about the immaterial world. Do
ideas, truths, logical relationships, etc., exist independently of a conscious mind? I don't know. If materialism is true,
mind does not exist independently of a brain, so we would at least have to have a material world to have an immaterial world.
This explanation seems most likely and has the most evidence in support of it. If one is a dualist, then mind exists independently
of the material world, but there is little support for that philosophy today; in fact, Daniel Dennett (1996, p. 24) says that
dualism has "been relegated to the trash heap of history," so this pretty well decides that question. The next question must
be: Does an immaterial world--with its ideas, truths, morals, etc.--exist independently of matter and energy? This is the
philosophy of idealism, which we can relegate in the same way as dualism, sensu Dennett. But the ultimate question
must be this: Does yet a third, transcendent world exist independently of both the material and immaterial natural worlds.
An affirmative answer to this question requires belief in supernaturalism, so the answer is probably no. [2]
Supernaturalists identify--misidentify, I believe--the immaterial world of the human mind, which obviously
exists and is part of nature, with the transcendental world of their supernatural beliefs. This practice is so pervasive that
I must discuss it here. Let us name and classify the three philosophical worlds and their elements: First, the material and
physical world of nature that includes matter and energy; second, the immaterial world of nature that includes mind, ideas,
values, imagination, logical relationships, etc.; third, the transcendental world of supernature that includes gods, spirits,
souls, etc. Belief in the first world with denial of the independence of the second constitutes materialism, belief in worlds
one and two constitutes naturalism, while belief in all three worlds constitutes supernaturalism. While the identification
of brain with conscious mind is relatively easy, supernaturalists identify conscious mind with soul. Similarly, naturalists
identify brain with imagination and emotion, but supernaturalists misidentify imagination and emotion as transcendence. Similarly,
brain is self becomes spirit; brain is dreams (or psychosis) becomes revelation; brain is imagined all-loving, all-powerful
authority figure becomes a deity; an unexplained natural phenomenon is a mystery becomes a miracle; a wrongful act is an immoral
act becomes a sin. In short, supernaturalists are exploiting the uncertainty and ignorance of science regarding the second
world of immaterial elements to create and justify their belief in a third world of supernature. Supernaturalists would object
to this analysis, I am sure, but it explains to me why they can continue to harbor their beliefs without empirical evidence--they
think they have evidence, but I think they are misinterpreting elements of the second world.
Science and Postmodernism
Science has, as have other intellectual disciplines, been challenged by postmodern thought. Such thought
questions whether human reason conforms to any objective standards of belief. Postmodernism says that there is no such thing
as objective, truthful knowledge in art, literature, history, philosophy, and even (or especially!) science. It seems useful
to briefly consider these concerns here. There are at least three criticisms postmodernists level against science:
Externalism -- The criticism that scientists are humans who perform their work within a culture or society, and
their findings and knowledge claims reflect that society and are motivated, determined, and legitimatized by cultural, economic,
gender, and political forces within that society, but external to science. Whatever biases or prejudices exist in a society
will be found in its science; thus, science and scientists have been racist, misogynist, sexist, anthropomorphist, jingoist,
mercantilist, etc.
Relativism -- The claim of scientists to an objective, progressive truth is refuted, according to postmodernists,
by the ever-changing nature of scientific truth: one theory replaces another, a paradigm becomes insupportable and is overthrown
by a competing paradigm in a scientific revolution. There is no objective truth, only subjective and relative truth that can
and will be succeeded by yet other subjective and relative truths. The relativity of truth and subjectivity of knowledge are
essential components of postmodernism to which science must respond. Indeed, postmodernism even challenges rationalism, the
possibility of humans being able to reason correctly to reach valid conclusions.
Subjectivism -- The idea here is that science is a human construct, not a system of reliable, objective knowledge
gained by application of a reliable method. Scientists, in this postmodern view, create their explanations, laws, and theories
by constructing a belief system, not by discovering them by using objective methods to analyze nature. Deconstruction focuses
on language and freeing it from concepts and referents; specifically, one cannot have confidence that meaning exists independently
of language, and therefore questions whether such words as "truth" have objective meaning. Deconstruction concludes that knowledge
or belief systems are unavoidably personal and subjective. In other words, scientists create their understanding of nature
by imposing their apriori, subjective beliefs, biases, assumptions, and presuppositions on nature, not by objectively and
disinterestedly investigating nature to discover what is there. Finally, deconstructionists analyze intellectual disciplines
by taking apart--deconstructing--the literature of that discipline, thus revealing its hidden, subjective meanings.
The postmodernist critique of science undoubtedly finds its strongest expression in the historicist
school of the philosophy of science, a movement opposed to the positivist school that was dominant until the early 1960s.
I have no trouble identifying Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend, and others as postmodernists, and although I acknowledge that
they poked holes in the remarkable edifice of positivism (logical positivism, logical empiricism) of Rudolf Carnap, Hans Reichenbach,
Carl Hempel, Ernest Nagel, and others, I am not convinced that positivism should be totally abandoned, as some suggest, but
only selectively abandoned. Logical positivism was prescriptive and ahistorical, and therefore unquestionably did not characterize
the true nature of science, but its emphasis on empirical evidence and logical structure cannot be discarded. Present-day
philosophers of science are attempting to forge a new, third-generation, synthetic philosophy of science based on the best
attributes of the previous two schools; this new school is called, remarkably enough, the naturalist school. This turn or
return to naturalism is now dominant among philosophers of science (Kitcher, 1992; Callebaut, 1993). These philosophers believe
that matters of fact are as relevant to philosophical theory as they are to science (a positivist stance), but they also claim
that the history of scientific discovery and theory formation is vital to understanding and explaining the workings of science
(an historicist stance). I think the naturalist school is a very positive development in the history of philosophy of science,
although I point out that they come to no agreements concerning the objectivity and credibility of science.
The surest sign that postmodernism is wrong is that postmodern critiques of science have had absolutely
no effect on the practice of science or the continuing achievements of science. If there had been any truth at all to postmodernism,
scientists would have changed their scientific methods and procedures to try to escape the postmodern pitfalls of relativism,
subjectivism, and externalism. The fact that few scientists know or care about postmodernism, and none have been influenced
by it, speaks volumes. (Karl Popper's neopositivistic falsificationism, on the other hand--and for better or worse!--has been
remarkably influential.) Some scientists have taken the time to understand postmodernism and, in their minds, it is easy to
refute (Gross and Levitt, 1994; Gross, Levitt, and Lewis, 1996). Although some philosophers probably don't believe this, scientists
are and have long been aware of the minefields of relativism, subjectivism, and externalism, and they firmly believe that
the scientific method, as it is now and as it has long been practiced, eliminates--not just minimizes--these problems. (Admittedly,
this process of elimination is historical and may take years, decades, or even centuries!) I have long believed this myself,
and now that I have become acquainted with the postmodern critiques of science, I still believe it. Avoiding relativism, subjectivism,
and externalism is what scientists learn in science school. The end result of the scientific method is the most reliable knowledge
that humans can possess, although not necessarily ultimate, absolutely true knowledge (whatever that means), but that is good
enough and better than the alternative.
Naturalism and Materialism
So many metaphysical naturalists believe in metaphysical materialism that naturalism and materialism
are often confused with each other. This confounding is not serious in most circumstances, but in this essay I must clarify
their distinctiveness to prepare for the discussion of the methodological/ontological assumption/necessity of naturalism in
science. The primary purpose of this paper is to examine the claims of Phillip Johnson (1990, 1991, 1994a, 1994b, 1995) and
the authors in The Creation Hypothesis (Moreland, 1994) that scientists, by advocating and teaching the fact of evolution,
are promoting the unconstitutional establishment of a religion (metaphysical naturalism) in the intellectual life of our country,
and that true, value-neutral (i.e. metaphysical-neutral) science should consider supernatural explanations as well as natural
ones. In her otherwise astute and highly critical review of Johnson (1990), Eugenie Scott repeatedly confounds naturalism
and materialism, and my agreement or disagreement with her depends on which one she really means, since her refutation of
Johnson's claims concerns on the problems I am addressing.
Her review (Scott, 1993, p. 43) of Darwin on Trial (Johnson, 1991) contains the following passage:
Johnson manages to set up another strawman that does not accurately reflect the real relationship between evolution
and religion. Evolution is presented as a "fully naturalistic process," implying an antithesis between evolution and the supernatural....Johnson
confuses the necessary methodological materialism (or naturalism) of science with philosophical materialism/naturalism.
Science neither denies nor opposes the supernatural, but ignores the supernatural for methodological reasons.
In an important paper, Scott (1996, p. 514-515) repeats this idea:
Creationists...claim that the rejection of the supernatural in modern science is a function of "naturalism" (materialism),
a philosophy that defines reality only in terms of material causes. Because evolutionary scientists supposedly are caught
up in a metaphysical viewpoint that rejects the possibility of a creator, creationists contend that evolutionists are unable
to countenance evidence for supernatural intervention in the history of life. Actually, modern science has omitted the supernatural
for methodological, not philosophical, reasons....[W]e simply get better explanations by ignoring the possibility of supernatural
intervention or causation. Much confusion exists between materialism as a philosophy, and the methodological
materialism that informs all of modern science. It is logically possible to decouple philosophical and methodological materialism,
and individual scientists who are believers do it all the time. Gregor Mendel was certainly not a metaphysical naturalist,
but he developed his understanding of the rules of heredity using methodological materialism....I stress methodological materialism
as a tool to understand the natural world better....
Naturalism is not a philosophy that defines reality only in terms of material causes. Again, in the same paper (p. 518):
First, science is a limited way of knowing, in which practitioners attempt to explain the natural world using natural
explanations. By definition, science cannot consider supernatural explanations...So by definition, if an individual is attempting
to explain some aspect of the natural world using science, he or she must act as if there were no supernatural forces operating
on it. I think this methodological materialism is well understood by evolutionists.
Again, in the same paper (p. 519):
Scientists, like other teachers, must be aware of the difference between philosophical materialism and methodological
materialism and not treat them as conjoined twins. They are logically and practically decoupled.
There is an important point in these quotations--the distinction between methodological and ontological
(Scott uses the term "philosophical") naturalism--and I do not want to see it lost by the practice of confusing naturalism
with materialism. Johnson, also, mistakenly conflates naturalism and materialism in a footnote (1995, p. 38): "'Naturalism'
is similar to 'materialism, ' the doctrine that all reality has a material base. I prefer the former term because it avoids
any confusion by the ordinary language distinction between matter and energy...." He uses the term naturalism exclusively
from then on, which makes his arguments quite clear (but not thereby valid). I don't think he needs to worry about confusion
between matter and energy; both of these are material, both being composed of elementary particles, as he recognizes. He is
also correct, as he states later in that footnote, that both naturalists and materialists understand nature to be "all there
is," but he is incorrect to state that they also understand nature to be "fundamentally mindless and purposeless." Humans
are both material and part of nature, and they are not mindless and purposeless. Presumably he means that, except for humans,
philosophical naturalists understand nature to be fundamentally mindless and purposeless, and here I agree.
The point in this section is this: Of course scientists adopt methodological materialism; probably
everyone in the world does, even metaphysical idealists. This is hardly controversial or interesting. Scientists are also
methodological monists and realists. Scientists and everyone else do not have the time to contemplate whether subatomic particles
or ideas and mind are primary, whether there is one ultimate substance or two, or whether the universe is real. (Materialism
is not, I wish to emphasize, an assumption or presupposition on the part of scientists; science would be equally valid if
idealism or dualism, rather than materialism, were true. I consider materialism to be a working hypothesis whose essential
validity has been corroborated by experience over the centuries.) The important question we face is the adoption of methodological
and ontological naturalism by science, which is certainly the real concern of Scott, Johnson, and myself, so let's
not confuse ourselves by using inaccurate terminology.
The Origin of Naturalism and Its Relation to Science
Science and naturalism are not the same thing. Science is a way of knowing, a powerful method that
uses three epistemologies in a unique and systematic way to discover the secrets of nature. Science is not metaphysical. Naturalism
is a philosophy, a metaphysics or ontology that posits a particular picture of reality, being, and existence that excludes
the supernatural. What is the origin of naturalism and its relationship to science? I can deal with these issue only briefly
and superficially.
Naturalism did not exist as a philosophy before the nineteenth century, but only as an occasionally
adopted and non-rigorous method among natural philosophers. It is a unique philosophy in that it is not ancient or prior to
science, and that it developed largely due to the influence of science. Naturalism begins with Galileo and Isaac Newton, who
began to explain nature by theoretical and experimental descriptions of matter and their motions. The outstanding success
of this method led others to emulate them, and a comprehensive understanding of the universe was initiated. Galileo and Newton
were not naturalists; they did not hesitate to attribute supernatural causes to things that they thought could not be explained
by natural causes. Until the late eighteenth century, most scientists agreed with them, but the influence of the Enlightenment
led scientists, such as Antoine Laurent Lavoisier, Pierre Simon de Laplace, and James Hutton to abandon all supernatural explanations
in favor of natural ones. Biology was the last science to be so treated, by Jean Baptiste Lamarck and Charles Darwin. I am
convinced that each of these men intentionally tried to be the Newton of his day--and science--by finding purely natural laws
to explain natural processes and objects.
Under the influence of philosophers John Herschel and William Whewell, methodological naturalism was
systematized and promulgated, so that, by the end of the nineteenth century, methodological naturalism was embedded in science.
Naturalism as a necessary part of science thus developed gradually as science developed gradually with the practice and understanding
of scientists. Appreciation of the hypothetico-deductive method and empirical-skeptical testing of hypotheses required naturalism,
since legitimate, scientific supernatural predictions cannot be made or supernatural conjectures tested. Holdout scientists
who persisted in using supernatural explanations were gradually abandoned intellectually by their students and colleagues,
and they eventually died with no successors. There was never a single moment or event when supernaturalism was evicted from
the structure of science and naturalism locked in. However, by the turn of the twentieth century, supernaturalism had been
methodologically eliminated and the scientific method came to be identified as naturalistic. The last legitimate creationist
scientists died around this time, and creationist pseudoscience was soon to be born. Thus, methodological naturalism became
historically an essential part of science.
Ontological naturalism developed from this methodological naturalism. Under the influence of Charles
Sanders Peirce, the first great American philosopher, naturalism developed--primarily in the United States--with the writings
of F. J. E. Woodbridge, Morris Cohen, John Dewey, Ernest Nagel, and Sidney Hook (Ryder, 1994). Naturalism, as a twentieth
century American philosophy, reached its zenith during the 1930s and 40s. It has been kept alive by the work of philosophers
Paul Kurtz (1990), Kai Nielsen (1996), and David Papineau (1993), and it is making a resurgence, in a less formal guise in
the philosophy of science, with the work of Michael Ruse (1986), David Hull (1988), Philip Kitcher (1992, 1993) , and others.
Explicitly naturalistic humanist authors such as Dewey, Hook, Kurtz, and others have developed a form called pragmatic naturalism,
which is much more than a straightforward ontological system, involving, as it does, ethical, social, and political components
in addition to metaphysical ones. As such, pragmatic naturalism more or less provides the philosophical underpinnings of naturalistic
humanism.
Naturalism is almost unique in that it would not exist as a philosophy without the prior existence
of science. It shares this status, in my view, with the philosophy of existentialism. Scientists first discovered the meaninglessness
and purposelessness of the mind-external universe, and established this fact in the philosophy of naturalism. For example,
a frequently quoted phrase describing the naturalistic view of existence is that of George Gaylord Simpson (1967, p. 345),
one of the great paleontologists and evolutionary scientists of this century; he said, "Man is the result of a purposeless
and natural process that did not have him in mind. He was not planned." This fact consequently forces humans, largely against
their wills, to deal with their unplanned existence by creating meaning and purpose entirely within their own minds by their
relations with other human minds, not a pleasant prospect or experience. (I have humorously labeled this insight, for what
it is worth, as "science precedes existence precedes essence.") Existentialism deals with human realization of the fact of
natural meaninglessness and purposelessness, and the task of accepting and overcoming it, if possible.
But none of this answers the main question: How important is methodological and ontological naturalism
for science to work and be successful? Must ontological naturalism be true or assumed to be true to practice science, or is
it irrelevant to the scientific method?
Methodological Naturalism and Ontological Naturalism
Is it true that science does not entail a belief in metaphysical naturalism, but only the temporary,
uncommitted adoption of methodological naturalism? Methodological naturalism is the adoption or assumption of naturalism in
scientific belief and practice without really believing in naturalism. Ontological naturalism (= metaphysical naturalism)
is the claim that naturalism is a descriptor of existence or reality, i.e. the act of sincerely accepting that naturalism
is true. (Ontology and metaphysics usually mean the same thing--a philosophical understanding of existence, being, and reality--so
naturalism can be prefaced by either "ontological" or "metaphysical" and mean, in the present context, that a person believes
in naturalism as the ontology or metaphysics that explains reality. I prefer not to use the term "philosophical naturalism"
in this context, since even a methodological naturalist is using naturalism as a philosophy--just not being sincere about
it.) One might say, "Isn't it rather silly to assume the truth of a philosophy, just for your scientific work or for scientific
beliefs about the universe, that you don't actually believe?" I do say it: I think such a stance is logically and morally
absurd, although I recognize it as legitimate in a certain pragmatic sense, which is to have it both way--to save appearances--always
a popular attitude among humans. But this is not the same as saying that science entails ontological naturalism.
Such a stance--methodological naturalism combined with supernaturalism--is perhaps the most popular
metaphysical position in the United States today. All theistic scientists adopt such methodological naturalism, as well as
the 40-50% of the U.S. population who believe in science, evolution, and also in God, the view known as "theistic evolution"
(all of these individuals would be metaphysical supernaturalists). Of the others, 40-50% believe in creationism and God (also
all supernaturalists), and the remaining 10%, including most scientists and many philosophers, are nontheist believers in
science and evolution (all metaphysical naturalists). Therefore, no more than 10% of Americans sincerely believe in ontological
naturalism; 90% are ontological supernaturalists with about half of these being methodological naturalists when it suits them.
These figures belie the notion that metaphysical naturalism is some sort of secular religion being
established in the public schools by atheistic scientists (Johnson, 1990, 1995). It should be obvious that metaphysical theistic
supernaturalism is the established civil religion in this country. What really bothers Phillip Johnson is that informed, educated,
scientifically-knowledgeable people--always a minority--are largely ontological naturalists and don't agree with his brand
of God-active-in-nature theism. We may dispose of his claim that metaphysical naturalism is an established civil religion
very easily. First, from the figures discussed above, naturalism is distinctly the minority position in our population by
a huge margin. Even among intelligent, educated people it is the minority philosophical position (this group, like most, is
not really knowledgeable about science and its philosophy).
Second, metaphysical naturalism is not a religion by any definition of religion, even the open-ended
ones, such as "the means by which one derives answers to ultimate questions." Although naturalism may answer most ontological
questions, this hardly exhausts the superset of "ultimate questions." The establishment clause of the First Amendment deals
with religions, not metaphysical philosophies. Naturalistic humanism, a world view that promotes metaphysical naturalism along
with other viewpoints (such as democracy, humanitarianism, and moral relativism), would be a better candidate for Johnson's
established religion, and its alleged religious status has been litigated in courts on a number of occasions and found to
be without foundation. Metaphysical naturalism makes no moral or normative statements, and it advances no social concerns,
both of which seem to me to be essential elements of any religion.
Third, if one really objects to the establishment of a philosophy in violation of the First Amendment,
why doesn't Professor Johnson rail against the establishment of metaphysical realism--not only in schools, but in all agencies
of the federal government and all U.S. corporations--and one that I would agree is insidiously and pervasively established.
What Professor Johnson really wants, of course, is to have his own brand of theism established rather than other brands of
theism and nontheism, and to achieve this he uses one of the oldest rhetorical tricks in the book: overstate your case by
claiming that the intellectual opposition has an advantage in numbers or power that must be opposed by the emotional and active
involvement of every reader or listener. He probably also claims the news media is overwhelming liberal--has he listened to
the radio or read a newspaper lately?
Let's get back to the main topic, one of legitimate disagreement and importance--the use of methodological
or ontological naturalism by scientists in practicing the scientific method. I extensively quoted Eugenie Scott above regarding
her use of the terms naturalism and materialism. Her main, quite valid point is that science adopts methodological naturalism--not
ontological naturalism. She says that science "neither denies nor opposes the supernatural, but ignores the supernatural
for methodological reasons," that "modern science has omitted the supernatural for methodological, not [ontological], reasons,"
that "it is logically possible to decouple [ontological] and methodological [naturalism], and individual scientists who are
believers do it all the time," and "by definition, science cannot consider supernatural explanations," so "if an individual
is attempting to explain some aspect of the natural world using science, he or she must act as if there were no supernatural
forces operating on it," i.e. by definition, science cannot consider the supernatural, so a scientist must adopt, at least,
methodological naturalism. Scott's viewpoint is extremely common among scientists and the informed public about how science
works; Frederick Grinnell (1994) also defends its use with good reasons I do not repeat here. Even Phillip Johnson (1994,
p. 15) says the following:
Methodological naturalism--the principle that science can study only the things that are accessible to its instruments
and techniques [and, I might add, to its method]--is not in question. Of course science can study only what science can study.
Methodological naturalism becomes metaphysical naturalism only when the limitations of science are taken to be limitations
upon reality.
Precisely. Science investigates the natural, the supernatural may exist as part of ultimate reality,
so let's not say that the natural is all that exists because that is what science investigates (Johnson (1995, p. 212) emphasizes
this point again in his latest book). There seems to be no question that scientists must, at a minimum, practice methodological
naturalism (but I will discuss objections to this statement below). Methodological naturalism in science seems to be acceptable
and uncontroversial. Not so, however, for the alleged link between science and ontological naturalism. Phillip Johnson, in
his many books and articles, maintains that teaching evolution as a fact of science establishes ontological naturalism in
intellectual society among people who would not and do not believe such a philosophy. Is he right?
Why does Genie Scott go to such great lengths to decouple the two aspects of naturalism? Her primary
reason is that she believes that this is the correct scientific and philosophical position, but the important second reason
is to protect the religious sensibilities of theistic evolutionists, the largest class of supporters of scientific evolution,
who also happen to be the largest class of opponents to scientific creationism. [3] She (1996, p. 518) takes William Provine, Paul Kurtz, and Daniel Dennett to task for promoting metaphysical naturalism and
materialism because they, she claims, argue that "Darwinism makes religion obsolete, and [they] encourage their colleagues
to argue likewise." However, I suspect that these individuals have many reasons for rejecting religion, or whatever specifically
they object to (since the word "religion" can refer to so many things), and I doubt that Darwinism (whatever that means) is
the sole reason.
Scott correctly argues (p. 519) that the naturalistic world of science precludes it from rejecting
the possibility of the supernatural. After stating her repeated distinction between ontological and methodological naturalism,
she says, "if it is important for Americans to learn about science and evolution, decoupling the two forms of [naturalism]
is essential strategy." In her conclusion (p. 520), she states the following:
I suggest that scientists can defuse some of the opposition to evolution by first recognizing that the vast majority
of Americans are believers, and that most Americans want to retain their faith. It is demonstrable that individuals can retain
religious beliefs and still accept evolution as science. Scientists should avoid confusing the methodological [naturalism]
of science with metaphysical [naturalism].
Protecting the religious sensibilities of theistic evolutionists seems a poor reason for insisting
that scientists decouple methodological and ontological naturalism in their explanation of science, and I also intensely dislike
referring to this as a "strategy," as if we are going to keep our followers in the fold by following a strategy. Scott's primary
reason, however, is to ask that scientists properly explain the scientific method. Science, an inanimate discipline, demands
methodological naturalism from its practitioners for science to work, and science could care less whether metaphysical naturalism
is true or not, or whether its practitioners believe it or not. Restricted to being a descriptor of science and the scientific
method, Scott's admonitions are unobjectionable and uncontroversial, and I fully support them.
Scientists and others who believe in science, however, are humans, and their beliefs are another story.
How convincing is the argument made by theistic naturalists, individuals who believe in both science and the supernatural,
that evolution--or any statement of science--is firmly established by a naturalistic method in which they don't really believe?
Not very convincing. I find difficulty with Scott's insistence that methodological and ontological naturalism are "logically
and practically decoupled." I maintain that the practice or adoption of methodological naturalism entails a logical and moral
belief in ontological naturalism, so they are not logically decoupled (but could remain practically or pragmatically decoupled
for those who wish). Most scientists presumably practice naturalism in science because they believe in naturalism as an ontology.
Theistic scientists, on the other hand, only assume--do not really believe--methodological naturalism, because they are actually
supernaturalists (this argument also applies to the much larger group of non-scientists who believe in both theism and scientific
evolution).
Do theistic scientists think they are playing a game, in which they do science during the day with
naturalistic methods, but at night go home and leave naturalism behind in the laboratory, since they don't really believe
it describes a true picture of reality? How can an individual scientist not believe that the work he or she is doing actually
discovers true and reliable knowledge about reality and still be motivated to perform that work? One might reply that his
or her work does indeed discover such reliable knowledge about a part of reality, the natural part, and the other, supernatural,
part is unknowable by science but presumably knowable by some other method (revelation, faith, authority, etc.). But this
distinction is based solely on a definition, not on any real knowledge of reality. In effect, it involves the identification
of the supernatural in a description of the realm of the natural, and thereby justifies one's adoption of methodological naturalism
by ignoring methodological naturalism. I think theistic/supernaturalistic methodological naturalists are being illogical in
this instance.
Theistic naturalists must believe in naturalism to methodologically assume or adopt it in science,
and they cannot logically maintain a belief in supernaturalism at the same time unless they maintain that there is absolutely
no connection at all between the natural and supernatural worlds. But this is something no supernaturalist maintains. Even
the most naturalistic theistic naturalist--a deist who claims that God is the ultimate Creator of the universe, but that everything
after that singular event is natural and operates by natural causes--believes in a supernatural origin of the universe. But
ontological naturalism makes no exception for the origin of the universe. It must have been natural, too. For supernaturalists
who believe in miracles or the dogmas of Christianity, the hurdle is even higher. It is not logically possible for them to
describe nature naturalistically when, in fact, they believe in supernatural violations of natural law, i.e. the manifestation
of miracles. These arguments suggest to me that methodological naturalism, itself alone required by science, is logically
untenable for humans unless one is simultaneously an ontological naturalist.
The moral entailment of ontological naturalism by methodological naturalism does not create an ethical
lapse among those supernaturalists who assume methodological naturalism, but something similar to an insincerity or want of
courage; theistic naturalists want to both believe in the claims of science--a prestigious, powerful, intellectual knowledge
system--but also want to escape the opprobrium of being known as ontological naturalists--that is, as atheists! Theistic naturalists
say, in effect, "I don't ultimately believe in naturalism, but I believe in the reliability of knowledge gained by its assumption,
and I expect you to believe in it too!" As with all moral arguments, one can accept or deny this argument on just about any
ethical basis, so I do not claim it has the same status as the logical arguments above. I merely want to suggest that supernaturalistic
methodological naturalists may wish to examine their metaphysical beliefs more closely, since I think they are illogically
engaging in self-deception. In the words of the Philosopher, "The unexamined life is not worth living." Theistic naturalists
might reply that, as a practical matter, they need to get on with their lives, practice and believe in science, live in communities
of theists and supernaturalists, and not really examine their metaphysical beliefs too closely, since life is too short for
indulging in such inconclusive intellectual activity. They might quote the words of Anonymous, "The unlived life is not worth
examining."
The power of science lies in the fact that it is not a metaphysics, but an epistemological method;
it has no prior commitment to a description of reality, being, or existence. It makes no assumptions and has no presuppositions
about its subject matter or methods. I fully realize that critics of science claim just the opposite: that science assumes
naturalism is true, that matter is real, that the universe is comprehensible, that natural laws are uniform through space
and time, and so forth (and if these assumptions were not made, science would be more open to supernatural hypotheses and
intelligent design, etc.). To assume the truth of any of these, in my opinion, would indeed make science a metaphysics. Instead,
science treats these high-level propositions as working hypotheses, what I would call metahypotheses. These metahypotheses
have themselves been repeatedly tested and corroborated throughout the centuries, and like other hypotheses in science, we
have great confidence that they are true. They can be considered reliable knowledge. The point is that everything in
science is hypothetical, the methods and rationales--the metahypotheses--as well as the objects and processes--the ordinary
hypotheses.
Of the various metahypotheses of science that have been overwhelmingly corroborated over the centuries,
certainly one of the most important is naturalism itself. This is undoubtedly a metaphysics, but it has been examined, tested,
and repeatedly corroborated. Isn't it ironic that theistic scientists and other supernaturalists feel that naturalism should
only be temporarily adopted in its methodological form, when it is now at least as reliable as everything else in science?
If they reject naturalism, what is their rationale for believing anything scientific? They could just as reasonably reject
it all.
In conclusion, while science as a process only requires methodological naturalism, I think that the
assumption of methodological naturalism by scientists and others logically and morally entails ontological naturalism. Although
I certainly recognize the possibility and practicality of decoupling methodological and ontological naturalism, I believe
assuming the truth of naturalism only for the purpose of conducting or believing science is a logical and moral mistake. I
would grant robots the status of being solely methodologically naturalistic, with no necessary commitment to ontological naturalism
and no concomitant logical and moral error--and since according to Daniel Dennett (1996) we humans are all robots anyway,
theistic naturalism may be okay after all!
Naturalism versus Supernaturalism in Science
We now turn to the other major topic of this paper, the claim by scientific creationists, theologians,
and philosophers who believe in theism and metaphysical supernaturalism that (1) supernaturalistic explanations are preferable
to some scientific naturalistic explanations, particularly concerning questions of origins, and that (2) scientists can and
should explain some natural phenomena by using supernaturalistic hypotheses within science (Thaxton, Bradley, and Olsen, 1984;
Geisler and Anderson, 1987; Johnson, 1990, 1991, 1994a, 1994b, 1995; Davis and Kenyon, 1993; Moreland, 1994; Behe, 1996).
Although, on their face, these suggestions sound preposterous (and I think they are preposterous), nevertheless they are serious
suggestions from authors who are able to make their cases with greater or lesser cogency, so they deserves a serious analysis
and refutation, which I can only initiate here in a somewhat general way.
The writers cited above have produced books that are different in many respects from the grossly pseudoscientific,
intellectually incompetent genre best exemplified by books from the Institute for Creation Research. While these titles are
more intelligently written and better argued, some of the authors, to a greater or lesser extent, make the same specious arguments,
indulge in the same misrepresentations of scientific information and misunderstandings of scientists and their writings, do
not understand or do not wish to acknowledge the now voluminous critiques published in recent years by evolutionary scientists
that explicitly refute creationist arguments, and continue to promote the same contempt for evolution that creationists always
have. While I cannot deal with such topics in this paper, I and others have done so in the past (references follow). Why don't
creationists attack something like thermodynamic theory or the theory of plate tectonics for a change? It is no fun to have
to spend time dealing with creationist literature, but the degree of understanding of science among the public is so small
that many people can be and are fooled by creationist arguments, so someone who understands the issues needs to deal with
it.
I view the method of critical inquiry (= critical thinking, scientific thinking, scientific method)
as the most reliable method of discovering truthful knowledge in any discipline, especially including science and philosophy.
Critical inquiry is the best truth-seeking, problem-solving method humans have to examine scientific hypotheses and theories,
evaluate competing truth claims, or establish the validity of a philosophy or philosophical position (I used it superficially
earlier to demonstrate the validity of naturalism). Along with Susan Haack (1996), I believe that truth matters in epistemology,
and we should understand what it means to claim to know truth. The truth that critical inquiry produces is called reliable
knowledge, knowledge that has a high probability of being true because it has been justified by a reliable method that uses
empiricism, rationalism, and skepticism. Without going into a lengthy analysis here of an understanding of critical inquiry
that I and many other scientists and philosophers have shared for years, let me just refer readers to a recent book that exemplifies
this method: The New Skepticism: Inquiry and Reliable Knowledge, by Paul Kurtz (1992). While the use of empiricism
and rationalism in science and philosophical inquiry have been around for years (centuries), participants in the modern skeptics
movement, including myself, have increasingly emphasized the skeptical (tentative, fallibilist) aspects of critical inquiry,
and the book by Kurtz presents a good summary of these ideas.
It is refreshing to state that, unlike theistic methodological naturalists, theistic metaphysical
supernaturalists who promote supernaturalism within science or instead of science engage in no logical or moral errors in
support of their beliefs: they unequivocally and explicitly support the action of supernaturalism in both nature and supernature.
What they wish to practice and promote, however, is not science, but pseudoscience. Science, as I hoped everyone understood
by now, requires at least methodological naturalism; supernatural explanations, therefore, are illegitimate. Perhaps I should
clarify this issue.
The boundary between science and pseudoscience is a problem for the philosophy of science, termed
the "demarcation problem." The argument is as follows: there is a continuum from normal science to frontier science, fringe
science, and pseudoscience, and the boundary between legitimate science and pseudoscience is not clearly known or defined.
I acknowledge and accept this problem of demarcation (I am familiar with the work of Larry Laudan and other philosophers of
science who explicitly discuss this problem; Laudan's articles are reprinted in Ruse, 1996a). I have sometimes wondered how
Michael Ruse would have testified about scientific method before Judge William Overton if the topic had been the constitutionality
of state legislation passed to ensure fair and balanced treatment for "punctuated equilibria along with the prevailing theory
of phyletic gradualism," or for "cold fusion along with the universally-accepted theory of thermodynamics," or for "extrasensory
perception along with the prevailing view of its absence within psychology." All three of these examples are legitimate demarcation
problems between science and pseudoscience, falling as they do among the categories of frontier and fringe science.
But I maintain that there is at least one criterion of legitimate science that correctly identifies
scientific creationism and all forms of supernatural explanation in science as pseudoscience. This is the criterion of testability.
It dates from the beginning of the nineteenth century when scientists began to explicitly eschew supernatural explanations,
and it was quickly recognized and identified in the work of the first philosopher of science, John Herschel, who is responsible
for first explicating the hypothetico-deductive method of science. It is now commonly accepted, for example, that Charles
Darwin deliberately used Herschel's characterization of correct scientific method in his effort to establish the fact and
his theory of evolution in 1859 (Ghiselin, 1969). In the twentieth century, Karl Popper championed and extended this same
idea in his work on prediction, deduction, testing, and falsification in science. I am completely aware that Popper's solution
to the demarcation problem is incomplete. (How would one apply it in the continuing controversy over the reality of ESP, for
example, when it is the very predictions, tests, and statistical degree of falsification that is under controversy?) I maintain,
however, that the criterion of testability or falsifiability is a necessary but not sufficient solution to the demarcation
problem, and while I admit it cannot distinguish science from pseudoscience in all areas of interest, the "necessity of being
susceptible to falsification" criterion is quite capable of eliminating all supernatural explanations, such as creationism
and intelligent design, from legitimate science--because such explanations cannot be falsified.
Pseudoscience is false science, an ideology masquerading as science. Often the ideology is religious,
as is the case with Christian fundamentalism, but sometimes it is political, such as is the case with Lysenkoism. There is
a very fine line between religious and political ideologies, and each adopts many of the characteristics of the other. For
example, scientific creationism can easily be considered a political movement, seeking, as it does, to gain intellectual respectability
by holding conferences at respected secular universities and gain access to public school textbooks and classrooms through
legislative efforts and the courts. For its case, Lysenkoism had the status of a cult within the religion of Soviet state
communism. Pseudosciences cannot be falsified because they claim supernatural, preternatural, and paranormal elements exist
and that these interact with the natural world, and the existence of these elements and the nature of their interactions with
the natural world cannot be investigated and tested by the naturalistic methods of science.
There are many other criteria that prove scientific creationism to be a pseudoscience, such as its
advocates failure to publish their work in the standard scientific literature, their misrepresentation of scientific information,
their use of specious and fallacious arguments, their continued ignoring or disbelieving of scientific refutations of their
claims, their flagrant mistakes, untruths, quotes out of context, and so forth (see Kitcher, 1982; Ruse, 1982; Futuyma, 1982;
and Godfrey, 1983, which contains my own contribution, Schafersman, 1983; for Johnson's Darwin on Trial, see Scott
and Sager, 1993, and Scott, 1993; for many of the other books, see NCSE, 1994). Some goals of creationist pseudoscience are
to subvert legitimate science in courts, legislatures, and school boards, to confuse the public about the methods and powers
of science, and especially to derogate the heroic accomplishments of science that demonstrate the overwhelming truth of evolution
(such as the finches of the Galapagos Islands (Weiner, 1994), the cichlid fish in Lake Victoria (Goldschmidt, 1996), the fruit
flies of the Hawaiian Islands, the whale, horse, reptile-to-mammal, hominid-to-human transitional sequences in the fossil
record, Cambrian fossils (Gould, 1990), etc.). These efforts are not only morally reprehensible, they are dangerous in an
age when viruses, bacteria, and insects are evolving rapidly due to human selection pressures--microbes may once again be
the primary agent of human population control.
For the purposes of this paper, however, I am only considering the failure of creationists to present
a scientifically-acceptable theory of creation, which I claim they have not done because it is impossible for them to do so
within legitimate science. Their solution to their very real, implicitly recognized, problem is to attempt to change the definition
of science to allow supernatural explanations. This reveals, I hope, the tremendous irony of the current attempts by creationist
and supernaturalistic philosophers to change the nature of science by forcing it to accept supernatural elements. The current
effort is the implicit admission by creationists that scientific creationism or intelligent design requires supernatural explanations
and that scientific creationism is not now part of science. For the current effort would not have to be made if either (1)
scientific creationism did not require supernaturalism or (2) scientific creationism was currently part of science. For decades,
scientific creationists have claimed that their ideology was scientific, and they have tried to force their doctrine into
public schools by the rationale that it is as scientific as evolutionary science. Scientists have repeatedly disputed these
claims; now, with their current efforts to create a supernaturalistic science, the creationists implicitly agree with us!
The scientific creationist political effort to have people believe that supernatural religious beliefs
are scientific is prompted by science's great intellectual legitimacy and prestige, brought about by its tremendous success.
People will naturally be attracted to such a knowledge system and thus be exposed to its associated philosophy of methodological
naturalism and the metaphysical consequences. Scientific creationism is a religio-political effort that tries to subvert science,
to create a misunderstanding in people's minds about the true nature of science. Scientific creationists accomplish this by
confusing people about how science works, the scientific method, the nature of scientific evidence, reasoning, and skepticism,
and the overwhelming evidence for evolution. Assaults on science textbooks, debates with scientists, creationist seminars
and presentations, and most spectacularly, the attempts to pass balanced treatment laws--all are aimed at reducing scientific
literacy among the lay public by promoting pseudoscience.
Scientific creationists in particular and scientific supernaturalists in general claim, of course,
that the new supernaturalistic science they propose does make predictive supernatural explanations based on good evidence,
that these explanations are legitimate scientific hypotheses that can be tested and falsified, and therefore the conclusions
they reach that invoke the supernatural can and should be considered legitimately scientific. This is the primary thesis of
the books cited above, and the explicit thesis in some of them, such as Moreland (1994). I strongly disagree with this claim.
Contrary to Larry Laudan, I do not consider scientific creationism to be merely "bad science"; parapsychology, cold fusion,
and many other topics are bad science--creationism is pseudoscience.
Larry Laudan (three papers reprinted in Ruse, 1996a) has contempt for the testability criterion, claiming
that many pseudosciences would be scientific under this criterion because they are, in principle, falsifiable, and their claims
have been falsified. He puts scientific creationism in this category. I am not sure if Laudan is as familiar with the creationist
literature as Michael Ruse and I, but he is wrong. I agree with Laudan that when pseudosciences like scientific creationism
make statements about the natural realm, such as a 6000-year old Earth or a specific fossil sequence, the predictions are
easily falsified. This is also true for the many other pseudosciences that Laudan identifies. If they restricted their predictive
"hypotheses" to the natural realm, used valid arguments, accepted empirical evidence to the contrary as valid, and agreed
that they would change their views if conflicting evidence was present, all of these pseudosciences would long ago have disappeared
because they would have been falsified. The reason they haven't vanished is because their proponents invariably make claims
that have supernatural, preternatural, and paranormal elements, and these elements cannot be tested and falsified,
so pseudosciences can persist just as Popper claimed (but then he once thought that modern scientific evolutionary theory
was unfalsifiable, so what does he know?).
Michael Ruse (1996b) uses a similar argument is his reply to Laudan; he quotes Duane Gish (1979) and
Henry Morris (1966) to the effect that the Creator used processes that "are not now operating anywhere in the natural universe,"
that we "cannot discover by scientific investigations anything about the creative processes used by the Creator," and "it
is...quite impossible to determine anything about Creation through a study of present processes..." I certainly agree with
these refreshingly candid, clear, but old statements; times change, and now the authors of The Creation Hypothesis
and Of Pandas and People insist that we can use the intelligent design hypothesis in science.
The Three Societies Argument
Supernatural creation requires a supernatural creator. Does the intelligent design hypothesis require
a supernatural creator? Yes and no! One can construct an argument for intelligent design as follows: There are on Earth many
animal societies that exist on a continuum from highly complex to very simple. Human society is complex and flatworm society
is simple. If flatworms had a science, they would comprehend humans as superflatworms--as Unseen Watchers, creators of microscopes
and petri dishes, despoilers of meadow ponds, givers of life and agents of death: able to snatch any flatworm from its pond
and take it to flatworm heaven. Perhaps they imagine that a human looks like a flatworm, but one with superflatworm powers:
transformer and manipulator of matter and energy, possessing seemingly instantaneous abilities of transport, all-powerful,
all-knowing, probably all-good, since flatworms would project their highest moral understandings onto their Human, and any
Human-caused injury to flatworm society (such as draining a pond) is all part of an ineffable plan. Flatworms would probably
consider their Human to be above flatworm nature, that is, supernatural from their point of view.
Now, let's consider a third society, one greater and more powerful than human society to the same
extent that human society is greater than flatworm society. This third society consists of extraterrestrial aliens living
somewhere in the universe. The product of billions of years of biological evolution, as with humans, but also millions of
years of cultural evolution and scientific accomplishment greater than humans. Their name is the Dogon. The Dogon aliens have
such an advanced technology that they have mastered the creation, transformation, and manipulation of matter and energy at
any magnitude. They can create and move stars and planets, or destroy them. Creating living organisms from lifeless molecules
is easy for them. They have even seeded simple life forms on suitable nearby planets and are studying the results, although
they are completely aware that it will take billions of years for anything really interesting to evolve. The Dogon technology
allows them to instantaneously travel throughout the universe, but the universe is so large that they have only explored a
very tiny portion of it. They have found no other intelligent life forms in the universe, since they haven't yet visited Earth.
While they have found living organisms on many other planets, not a single one has animals that have developed a technology.
An important aphorism states that, "Any sufficiently advanced technology is indistinguishable from
magic." I revise this as follows: "Any sufficiently advanced technology is indistinguishable from miracles." Magic is illusion,
deception, and we are considering the real thing here. The Dogon are obviously superhuman; their technology allows them to
perform miracles from a human perspective: they can levitate, turn chemicals into life, revive dead organisms with their medicine,
instantaneously transport themselves through time and space, transform matter and energy into any form, extend their minds
by extrasensory perception--in short, they are all-powerful and all-knowing by human standards. In addition, they long ago
discovered the advantages of removing evil from their society, so they are also all-good.
How would the Dogon appear to us? They are unquestionably Intelligent Designers. They are completely
natural, and if we knew something about them, we could legitimately specify their activities in our scientific theories about
nature. In fact, we would be obligated to, as obviously would flatworms about humans in flatworm scientific theories. If flatworms
were conscious, they would have to be aware of humans--how could they miss us? Humans would pervade their scientific understanding
of nature. If the Dogon existed and we were aware of them, the same would be true of our scientific understanding of nature.
We would be obligated to hypothesize at least one Intelligent Designer--maybe more. That's the wonderful thing about the intelligent
design hypothesis--you don't have to stop at one. There could be many Intelligent Designers. And, since some of the Dogon
are not as thoughtful or careful as others, one can hypothesize an Unintelligent Designer (perhaps it was this Dogon who designed
the close proximity of human reproductive organs to the systems that eliminate metabolic wastes).
If we knew of the Dogon aliens, we could explain so much. The possibilities would be endless for scientifically
legitimate naturalistic explanations involving an intelligent designer. So why don't scientists use intelligent design explanations.
Because we know of no Dogon. There is no empirical evidence for them, and no reason to believe in them despite the lack of
evidence. Naturalistic explanations do an excellent job of explaining a great deal about nature, including the presence in
our bodies of a sewage disposal pipeline in the middle of a major recreational area. Scientists don't use supernaturalistic/intelligent
design explanations because naturalistic explanations have been so successful, and we have confidence that they will continue
to be successful in those frontier areas that currently have no really good, widely-accepted theories, such as origin of life
and origin of universe questions.
There is no way for supernaturalists to establish the truth of an intelligent design hypothesis using
the methods of science. I maintain that it is impossible, in principle, for natural evidence and arguments to demonstrate
the existence of anything supernatural, such as creation, intelligent design, or a god. In order to demonstrate the reality
of such supernatural processes or entities in this way, one would have to know the relationships or interactions between the
natural and supernatural, and we don't know these. Furthermore, by the methods of science, we can't know these relationships
anymore than we can know the supernatural elements. Attempts at explaining these relationships have included natural theology
(classical arguments from design) and the anthropic cosmological principle, neither of which has succeeded. Modern attempts
using intelligent design or creation hypotheses will likewise fail, because in essence these are all god-of-the-gaps explanations,
attempts to use God or an Intelligent Designer to explain current natural mysteries that seemingly have science stumped, such
as the origin of life, the origin of the universe, the origin of phyla in the Cambrian, and so forth. When natural scientists
succeed in solving any natural mystery, that gap vanishes and the available room for the intelligent designer becomes smaller.
Simple lack of knowledge for some natural process or event is not sufficient to justify a supernatural explanation. Frankly,
I consider these god-of-the-gaps creationist arguments to be unworthy of modern analysis. So the use of natural evidence and
arguments to demonstrate the existence of the supernatural is not sound.
A major problem for intelligent creation and design advocates is that before they can use the hypothesis
of a creator or intelligent designer in their hypotheses, they must first demonstrate its existence. Premises of logical arguments,
which is of course what predictive scientific hypotheses are, must be true if the conclusion is to be true. The terms "creator"
and "intelligent designer" are currently as devoid of comprehensibility as the term "god." Before these terms can be used
in scientific hypothetical premises, they must first be found in a conclusion that does not assume their existence. But no
one has ever produced such a valid argument, either scientifically or logically. Since I argued in the previous paragraph
that natural, scientific evidence could not be expected to demonstrate the existence of a creator or intelligent, I see no
alternative but the use of logical, rational arguments to do this. There are ontological arguments that purport to establish
the existence of God (Plantinga, 1967; but see Oppy, 1996, for a reply), and I see these as far superior to natural ones.
The problem of "origins" is the main area that creationists and intelligent design proponents see
as the difficulty for naturalistic science. Efforts were made (Thaxton et al., 1984; Geisler and Anderson, 1987) to identify
two different kinds of science, "operations science" and "origins science." The distinction that these authors make deals
with natural phenomena that occur "with regularity" and those that occur "singularly." Regularly-occurring phenomena can be
studied by operations science, essentially the normal, legitimate science we have today. But singular phenomena, such as the
origin of species, of life, the Earth, the solar system, the galaxy, and the universe, can only be studied by origins science.
Furthermore, these authors maintain that there are also two different causes in operation in nature, primary causes and secondary
causes. Thaxton et al. (1984) explicate identify the primary cause as the "God hypothesis," and while agreeing that using
this primary cause in operations science is not permissible, in origins science it is not only permissible, but essential,
since God would have willed many singular natural effects using supernatural causes, i.e. miracles.
Needless to say, this two-faced science is a false dichotomy: there is no split in science between
singular and repeatable phenomena. There are a number of reasons for this, but basically it boils down to the following: all
phenomena in nature are singular, and all are repeatable. The component parts or steps of a repeating or regular phenomenon
can be examined as if each was a singular event (such as the movements of electrons between shells of different energies),
and every singular event is merely an example of a class of singular events that are essentially identical (such as a speciation
event). The only exception to this refutation is, of course, the singular origin of the universe. Why is there something rather
than nothing? I have no answer to this question. But I will state that the dichotomous operations-origins science proposal
is not going to work.
Scientific hypotheses must contain a cause and effect relationship within their predictive explanations.
Testing the explanatory predictive hypothesis requires understanding the hypothesis. Invoking a supernatural intelligent designer
destroys the cause and effect relationship of any deductive scientific hypothesis, preventing us from understanding the hypothesis,
as thus disallowing it as really explanatory. So, I would accept the hypothesis of a purely natural creator/intelligent designer--such
as the Dogon--if one was necessary, but as Laplace would say, I have no need for that hypothesis. As for the hypothesis of
a supernatural creator/intelligent designer, I have no use for that hypothesis.
Endnotes
[1] This wonderful verse from Faust, Part 1, lines 1851-1855, expresses Goethe's view of human reason and science,
and the result of its abandonment by proponents of superstition. It also succinctly expresses the theme of this paper. The
verse has been translated in a variety of ways. Walter Kaufmann (1961, p. 195) gives it as follows in a rhyming translation:
Have but contempt for reason and for science,
Man's noblest force spurn with defiance,
Subscribe to magic and
illusion,
The Lord of Lies aids your confusion,
And, pact or no, I hold you tight.
Stuart Atkins (1994, p.47), in a more literal, non-rhyming translation, presents it as follows:
Scorn learning, if you must, and reason,
the highest faculty mankind possesses,
let your fondness for self-deception
involve
you deeper still in magic and illusion,
and its dead certain you'll be mine!
My own entirely naturalistic translation follows. Goethe, no supernaturalist, used the word geist in many ways,
referring not just to spirit or transcendental being, but also to human emotion or psyche (spirit in a materialist sense).
Self-deception is therefore an excellent translation of Lügengeist, "lying spirit," meaning Mephistopheles himself
in the literal context, for he is the supreme geist of the tragedy, the personification of that lying spirit within
humans: self-deception and psychologically-unacknowledged misunderstanding.
Despise reason and science,
humanity's greatest strengths,
indulge in illusions and magical practices
that
reinforce your self-deception,
and you will be unconditionally lost!
[2] I can't say "certainly no," as much as I would wish to, for I must be agnostic about the supernatural because I
have no knowledge of it. In addition, I don't believe in the supernatural, so I am also an asupernaturalist, i.e. a philosophical
naturalist. The reason for this is a simple application of critical thinking: there is no empirical evidence for the supernatural
and no reason to believe in it despite the lack of evidence, so skepticism demands that one not believe in it. The same arguments
hold true for theism. A common misunderstanding is that agnosticism is an intermediate position between theism and atheism,
but nothing is more mistaken. Atheism and agnosticism are not mutually exclusive. Atheism is the simple nonbelief in a god;
the term for believing that a god does not exist is antitheism. I personally know many of the most eminent atheists on this
planet, and none of them claim that a god does not exist; they are agnostic on that subject. We may be antitheistic about
specific gods, such as Allah, Jehovah, and the Christian God, but not about a god in general. Many less well-informed atheists
prefer to be called agnostic instead of atheist because of the well-known pejorative association; perhaps, as a self-descriptor,
they would prefer the term "nontheist," which doesn't sound so bad.
[3] So willing is Eugenie Scott to protect theistic supporters of evolution, that she quite unjustly rebukes Douglas
Futuyma and George Gaylord Simpson for making over-generalizations about reality and presenting their metaphysical philosophies
in the guise of science. She writes (Scott, 1996, p. 519):
To further defuse the religious issue, scientists can be more careful about how they use terms. For example, evolutionists
sometimes confuse the evidence we have for considerable contingency during the course of evolution with evidence for a lack
of ultimate purpose in the universe. Futuyma [1982] writes,
Perhaps most importantly, if the world and its creatures developed purely by material, physical forces, it could not
have been designed and has no purpose or goal....Some shrink from the conclusion that the human species was not designed,
has no purpose, and is the product of more material mechanisms--but this seems to be the message of evolution.
G. [G.] Simpson [1967] is regularly quoted with dismay by creationists as saying "Man is the result of a purposeless
and natural process that did not have him in mind. He was not planned." A theist might respond that we do not know what God's
purpose is or what [H]e planned. It is possible that if there is a...deity, it was part of its plan to bring humans and every
other species about [by evolution]. Of course, this would be a theological statement, but that, indeed, is the point. Saying
that "there is no purpose in life" is not a scientific statement. We are able to explain the world and its creatures using
materialist, physical processes, but to claim that this then requires us to conclude that there is no purpose in nature steps
beyond science into philosophy.... [I]n my opinion, for a nonreligious [she means someone who is a metaphysical naturalist]
professor to interject his own philosophy into the classroom in this manner is as offensive as it would be for a fundamentalist
professor to pass off his philosophy as science.
It should be obvious that Eugenie Scott is confusing categories here. The statements of Futuyma and
Simpson are completely correct and scientific: there is no purpose in nature, and humans were not planned or designed. (We
are all intentionally ignoring human purpose, of course). This is one of the supreme discoveries of science, and to suggest
that scientists engage in self-censorship to protect the religious sensibilities of theistic naturalists (evolution's most
numerous supporters and scientific creationism's greatest enemy) is not right. Neither author above said or knows whether
there is a supernatural purpose: they were both speaking from a completely scientific point of view. They don't deny that
there might be a supernatural purpose. I am sure they would say that if supernaturalists want to believe there is such a purpose,
let them believe it, but don't try to say that such a purpose exists in nature--it doesn't, as science has revealed. Simpson
and Futuyma are both ontological naturalists, but they were not trying to pass off their philosophy as science. They were
only speaking about what science knows about nature, and everything they say in the quotations above is completely correct
and proper. It is not "philosophy" to say there is no purpose in nature: this is a scientific fact. The worst they are guilty
of is promoting methodological naturalism, but I don't see how any scientist, even theistic ones, can escape doing this.
There is another, more subtle error in Scott's remarks that I cannot pass over. I am sure that both
Futuyma and Simpson know about contingency in evolution and did not confuse it with the "lack of ultimate purpose in the universe."
The lack of cosmic purpose in nature does not depend solely on the fact of evolutionary contingency. Simpson, as a matter
of fact, was the first author to explicitly identify and discuss the evolutionary implications of contingency (1967). Subsequently,
Ernst Mayr did also, and today we know about this quite important element of evolutionary theory from the writings of Stephen
Jay Gould, for example, his book Wonderful Life (1990).
References
Atkins, Stuart, editor and translator, 1994, Faust I & II, Vol. 2 of Goethe: The Collected Works,
Princeton University Press.
Audi, Robert, 1984, "Naturalism," in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, p. 372-374.
Behe, Michael J., 1996, Darwin's Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution, The Free Press.
Buell, Jon, and Virginia Hearn, editors, 1994, Darwinism: Science or Philosophy, Foundation for Thought and Ethics.
Callebaut, Werner, 1993, Taking the Naturalistic Turn, or How Real Philosophy of Science is Done, University
of Chicago Press.
Danto, Arthur C., 1967, "Naturalism," in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, p. 448-450.
Davis, Percival, and Dean Kenyon, 1993, Of Pandas and People: The Central Question of Biological Origins, Second
Edition, Haughton Publishing Co.
Dennett, Daniel C., 1991, Consciousness Explained, Little, Brown.
Dennett, Daniel C., 1996, Kinds of Minds: Toward an Understanding of Consciousness, BasicBooks.
French, Peter A., Theodore E. Uehling, Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein, 1994, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Volume
19: Philosophical Naturalism, University of Notre Dame Press.
Futuyma, Douglas J., 1982, Science on Trial: The Case for Evolution, Pantheon Books (1995, Sinauer Associates,
Inc.)
Geisler, Norman L., and J. Kerby Anderson, 1987, Origin Science: A Proposal for the Creation-Evolution Controversy,
Baker Book House.
Ghiselin, Michael T., 1969, The Triumph of the Darwinian Method, University of California Press (1984, University
of Chicago Press).
Gish, Duane, 1979, Evolution: The Fossils Say No!, Third Edition, Creation Life Publishers.
Godfrey, Laurie, editor, 1983, Scientists Confront Creationism, W. W. Norton & Co.
Goldschmidt, Tijs, 1996, Darwin's Dreampond, The MIT Press.
Gould, Stephen Jay, 1990, Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of History, W. W. Norton & Co.
Grinnell, Frederick, 1994, "Radical Intersubjectivity: Why Naturalism Is an Assumption Necessary for Doing Science,"
in Buell and Hearn, p. 99-106.
Gross, Paul R., and Norman Levitt, 1994, Higher Superstition: The Academic Left and its Quarrels with Science,
The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Gross, Paul R., Norman Levitt, and Martin W. Lewis, editors, 1996, The Flight From Science and Reason, The New
York Academy of Sciences.
Haack, Susan, 1996, "Concern For Truth: What It Means, Why It Matters," in Gross, Levitt, and Lewis, p. 57-63.
Hull, David L., 1988, Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science,
University of Chicago Press.
Johnson, Phillip E., 1990, "Evolution as Dogma: The Establishment of Naturalism," p. 1-17, Foundation for Thought and
Ethics special publication, Haughton Publishing Co.
Johnson, Phillip E., 1991, Darwin on Trial, InterVarsity Press.
Johnson, Phillip E., 1994a, "Darwinism's Rules of Reasoning," in Buell and Hearn, p. 6-20.
Johnson, Phillip E., 1994b, "Darwinism and Theism," in Buell and Hearn, p. 42-49.
Johnson, Phillip E., 1995, Reason in the Balance, InterVarsity Press.
Kaufmann, Walter, translator, 1961, Goethe's Faust, Doubleday & Co.
Kitcher, Philip, 1982, Abusing Science: The Case Against Creationism, MIT Press.
Kitcher, Philip, 1992, "The Naturalists Return," Philosophical Review, vol. 101, p. 53-114.
Kitcher, Philip, 1993, The Advancement of Science, Oxford University Press.
Kurtz, Paul, 1990, Philosophical Essays in Pragmatic Naturalism, Prometheus Books.
Kurtz, Paul, 1992, The New Skepticism: Inquiry and Reliable Knowledge, Prometheus Books.
Lacey, Alan R., 1995, "Naturalism," in The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, Ted Honderich, editor, p. 604-606,
Oxford University Press.
Luntley, Michael, 1995, Reason, Truth and Self: The Postmodern Considered, Routledge.
Moreland, J. P., 1994, The Creation Hypothesis, Scientific Evidence for an Intelligent Designer, InterVarsity
Press.
Morris, Henry M., 1966, Studies in the Bible and Science, Presbyterian and Reformed Publishing Co.
NCSE, 1994, Reviews of Creationist Books, National Center for Science Education.
Nielsen, Kai, 1996, Naturalism Without Foundations, Prometheus Books.
Oppy, Graham, 1996, Ontological Arguments and Belief in God, Cambridge University Press.
Papineau, David, 1993, Philosophical Naturalism, Blackwell.
Plantinga, Alvin, 1967, God and Other Minds: A Study of the Rational Justification of Belief in God, Cornell
University Press.
Post, John F., 1995, "Naturalism," in The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Robert Audi, editor, p. 517-518,
Cambridge University Press.
Ryder, John, 1994, American Philosophic Naturalism in the Twentieth Century, Prometheus Books.
Ruse, Michael, 1982, Darwinism Defended: A Guide to the Evolution Controversies, Addison-Wesley.
Ruse, Michael, 1986, Taking Darwin Seriously: A Naturalistic Approach to Philosophy, Blackwell.
Ruse, Michael, editor, 1996a, But Is It Science: The Philosophical Question in the Creation/Evolution Controversy,
Prometheus Books.
Ruse, Michael, 1996b, "Pro Judice," in Ruse, 1996a, p. 356-362.
Schafersman, Steven D., 1983, "Fossils, Stratigraphy, and Evolution: Consideration of a Creationist Argument," in Godfrey,
p. 219-244.
Simpson, George Gaylord, 1967, The Meaning of Evolution, Yale University Press.
Scott, Eugenie C., 1993, "Darwin Prosecuted," Review of Darwin on Trial by Phillip Johnson, Creation/Evolution,
Issue 33, p. 36-47.
Scott, Eugenie C., 1996, "Creationism, Ideology, and Science," in Gross, Levitt, and Lewis, p. 505-522.
Scott, Eugenie C., and Thomas C. Sager, 1992, Review of Darwin on Trial by Phillip Johnson, Creation/Evolution,
Issue 31, p. 47-56.
Sorell, Tom, 1991, Scientism: Philosophy and the Infatuation with Science, Routledge.
Thaxton, Charles B., Walter L. Bradley, and Roger L. Olsen, 1984, The Mystery of Life's Origin, Philosophical
Library.
Weiner, Jonathan, 1994, The Beak of the Finch: A Story of Evolution in Our Time, Alfred E. Knopf.
Rare Books
1. The Education Commission And After - J.P. Naik
Organization and finance
In India the responsibility for administering and financing education must vest in a number of official agencies begining
with the small or local community at one end and rising through the district school board and state goverment
to the Central government at the other; even voluntary private enterprise has a limited and minor but useful role to play.In
a national system of education two important things have to be done (I) the administrative responsibilities of these
agencies should be defined and (ii) as the educational responsibilities at the lower levels are much greater and
the avilabilty of resources is much larger at the higher levels an adequate system of grant in aid and devolution of resources
has to be designed so that the educational reponsibilities at each level are matched with the resources available.
(1) Central government Education should continue to be basically a state responsibiltiy as provided in the constitution .
while it was not in favour of including education in the concurrent list it was also not in favour of state absolutism in
education. It therefore provided significant roles to the central bodies on one hand and to the local bodies on the
other.
(2) State government The state government should determine their educational policies within the broad framework
of the national policy on education and in reponse to local needs and conditions.. Each state should pass a comprehensive
education act to embody and implement these policies.
(3) Local Authorities The commission recommended the establishment of district school boards and municipal
school boards which should have the authority to plan administer and develop all school education in their areas.There
should be adequate devolution of resources to match responsibilties entrusted to these organizations.Equalization
should be adopted as an overriding criterion.
(4) Private enterprise The growing educational needs of a modernizing society can only be met by the state and it
would be a mistake to show any over dependence on private enterprise . However minorities have certain educational rights
guaranteed in the constitution and they should be respected . Private enterprise has a right to exist in a democratic
society.Steps will be taken to merge all private educational institutions which seek financial asistance from
the state in the common school system.
(5) Administration Admnistrative structures at all levels will have to be revamped . It suggested the creation of
the Indian Educational Service , National Staff College for Educational Planners and Administrators, NCERT, State Councils
and improvement of the State Educational Department.
(6) Finance The Commission felt that a national system of education will need a much higher level of financial support
.It said that 4000 crore should be spent on education by 1986.
(7) Sectoral Priorities Total expenditure should be divided almost equally between different sectors ,elementary
, secondary ad higher education.
(8) Fees Fees should not be a source of revenue. All fees to be abolished till clas X. Free education to cover
all meritorious students in higher secondary and higher education Level.
(9) Economy and utilization Intensive efforts should be made to cut down unit costs , to economize in every way
possible and optimize utilization of existing facilities and to raise resources from voluntary and community contributions.
Rare Book II
2.The New Education Policy in India
By P.D.Shukla
Resources and Review
The Education Commission of 1964-66 , The National Education Policy of 1968 and practically all others concerned with education
have stressed that the egalitarian goals and the practical development oriented objectives of india society can be realized
only by making invetments in education of an order commensurate with the nature and dimensions of the task.
Resources to the extent possible will be raised by mobilizing donations , asking the beneficiary communities to maintain
school buidings.and supplies of some consummables , raising fees at the higher levels of education and effecting some savings
by the efficient use of facilities .Institutions involved with the research and development of technical and scientific manpower
should also mobilze some funds by levying a cess or a charge on the user agencies, including government departments and entrepreneurs
. All these measures will be taken not only to reduce the burden on state resources but also for creating a greater sense
of responsibility within the educational system. However such measures will contribute only marginally to the total
educational funding . The government and the community in general will find funds for programmes such as universalization
of elementary education,liquidating illiteracy , equality of access, educational opportunities to all sections throughout
the country , enhancing the social relevance , quality ad functional effectiveness of educational programmes , generating
knowledge and developing technologies in scientific fields crucial to self sustaining economic development and creating a
critical consciousness of the values and imperatives of national survival.
The deleterious consequences of non investment or inadequate investment in education are indeed very serious.Similarly
the cost of neglecting vocational and technical education and research is also unacceptable . Sub optimal performance in these
field s could cause irreparable damage to the Indian economy . The network of institutions set up from time to time since
independence to facilitate the application of science and technology would need to be substantially and expeditiously updated
, since they are fast becoming obsolete.
In view of these imperatives education will be treated as a crucial area of investment for national development and survival.The
National policy of education 1968 had laid down that the investment in eucation be gradually increased to reach a level of
expenditure of 6% of the national income as early as possible. Since the actual level of investment has remained far short
of that target , it is important that greater determination be shown now to find funds for the programmes laid down in this
policy . While the actual requirements will be computed from time to time based on monitoring and review the outlay on education
will be stepped up to the extent essential for policy implementation.It will be ensured that from the eighth five year plan
onwards it will uniformly reach 6% of the national income.
Review
The implentation of the various parameters of the New Policy must be reviewed every five years.Appraisals at short intervals
will also be made to ascertain the progress of implementation and the trends emerging from time to time.